Saturday, June 26, 2010

The Rage Against God

Peter Hitchens has published an insightful book, drawing on his own experience as former atheist and brother of a famous New Atheist. The Rage Against God is interesting both 1) for its discussion of atheism and atheism's links to intolerance, violence, and totalitarianism and also 2) for its portrait of the disintegrating world of postwar England in which he and I and also Roger Scruton grew up. (See Scruton's Gentle Regrets and England: An Elegy.)

Amazon has a brief clip in which Hitchens talks about the book at:
http://www.amazon.com/gp/mpd/permalink/m582FJ1QOUGY1

The Rage Against God: How Atheism Led Me to Faith
Gentle Regrets (Thoughts from a Life)
England: An Elegy

Friday, June 25, 2010

Dads, Don't Go

Joe Carter
June 25, 2010

“Are fathers necessary?” asks Pamela Paul in the latest issue of The Atlantic. That she considers the question worth asking is a clue to how the article will conclude: “there’s nothing objectively essential about his contribution.”

Published just before Father’s Day, it would be easy to dismiss such cheap contrarianism as an attention-getting stunt. (The empirical claims presented in Paul’s article—and the research it was based on—have been adequately rebutted. W. Bradford Wilcox and others have already pointed out that most of the studies relied upon small, unrepresentative samples of same-sex and heterosexual couples.) But the fact remains that in America we act as if fathers are unnecessary. We enjoy a fit of pique when Heather has two full-time mommies, yet only respond with a sad shrug when Heather has one part-time daddy. But if fathers are necessary, they have to be completely involved in the lives of their children—and living at home with their children’s mothers.

As David Blankenhorn notes in Fatherless America: Confronting Our Most Urgent Social Problem, “The evidence shows that the great majority of visiting fathers are not—indeed, cannot be—good-enough fathers to their children. The deck is stacked against them. Too much has changed, too fast; too much will continue to change.” In theory, he continues, it may be possible to restructure everything else about a family while maintaining fatherhood as a constant. In practice, it is hardly ever possible. Visiting fathers have lost the bases of fatherhood. As Bronislaw Malinowski put it in his classic cross-cultural analysis of parenthood, “the child is linked to both its parents by the unity of the household and by the intimacy of daily contacts.” But for the Visiting Father, both aspects of this linkage are irrevocably shattered.
I first read that passage in 1995, the year I myself became a “weekend dad.” In February my wife told me she was gay. In March she left our home and took my daughter with her.

At the time I was on recruiting duty for the Marine Corps, on an unforgiving assignment that required working fourteen-hour days, six days a week. I could only see my little girl on Sundays after making the ninety-mile trek from Olympia to Everett, where my soon-to-be-ex-wife had moved.

I’d pick up my two-year-old daughter, strap her into the car seat, and we’d set out on our weekend routine: to the park, if it was sunny and warm; to the play-land at McDonalds if it was rainy and cold. (In Everett, it is always rainy and always cold.)

Over the next several years, I was the one who moved—to Japan, San Diego, Dallas, Chicago, and Washington, D.C. I went from being “weekend dad” to being “summer-and-holiday dad.” Through it all I tried my best to be a “good-enough father.”

A few years ago I met Blakenhorn and talked to him about his book. I wanted to tell him that he was wrong. I wanted to tell him the base isn’t always lost and that the linkage is not always shattered. I wanted to tell him that it was indeed possible—because I was one—to be a “good-enough father.”

But it isn’t true. As much as I wanted to believe otherwise, Fatherless America was devastatingly prescient about my own experience as a “visiting father.” My experience was one more data point in the reams of empirical studies that show what millions of part-time dads before me have learned: Our children always need more than we can give them in a few weekend hours.

Of course, visiting fathers aren’t the only ones aware of the damage being done to our country’s children. Almost everyone acknowledge the harm in treating dad as if there is “nothing objectively essential about his contribution.”

Yet if we’re too specific, too personal, we may offend some poor hapless father who is doing the best he can. And who are we to judge any individual’s family situation? America’s true religion—unfettered individualism—requires that we find some way to justify everyone’s choice and ignore or play down the damage that results from such choices.

Although it is tempting to join in bending a knee to the cult of individualism (I’m an American, after all), I want to take a different approach. I want to directly address the specific, narrow audience who can do more than anyone else to change this destructive cycle. I want to make a policy proposal to the fathers who are on the verge of leaving their families.

As with all policy proposals, certain assumptions must be shared before agreement can be reached. My proposal is based on a simple argument: When your first child is born, your life stops being about what you want and starts being about what they need. If you disagree, you can stop reading now.

Here is the only way to fix the problem of fatherlessness: You must find a way to stay with your children. You may be having a tough time in your marriage. You may be thinking that you no longer love or can live with your spouse. You may believe that divorce is the only remaining option.

I don’t know your situation. I don’t know what you are going through. I only know that your children need you at home. Your sons and your daughters need your presence. They need you around, all the time, and not just for regularly scheduled visits. If you want to be a good father, don’t leave your children.

I’m fully aware that such a suggestion will be unpopular and that it will be deemed impractical. Our society tells us that you shouldn’t “stay together just for the kids.” Some social scientists will tell us that staying in an unhappy marriage will hurt the kids. Our culture tells us that progress has made fatherhood a vestigial artifact. Our hearts tell us that we deserve to pursue our own bliss. Even our churches can tell us that marriage is about being happy and that we deserve to be happy no matter what.

But again: When your first child is born, your life stops being about what you want and starts being about what they need. They need you at home. If you’re a good man and aspire to be a good father, that is all you need to know.

If your wife is physically abusive to you and the children, you need to get out—and take your kids with you. Otherwise you stick it out, and try to love your wife in every way possible. Maybe the marriage will heal (they sometimes do). Maybe it won’t. It doesn’t matter. If you have to stay in your marriage for one year or for eighteen, you stick it out until your children are grown.

What do you do, though, if you’re wife wants a divorce? You beg her to stay. You change what you have to change. You use guilt if necessary, and try to get her to “think about what is best for the kids.”

If nothing else works, then you ask her to commit to six months of marital counseling before she files for divorce. If at the end of the six months she’s still resolved to end the marriage you ask for another six months. You keep asking for as long as it takes. You may lose the fight eventually, but if you’re a man you will not give up on your family until you are bloodied and broken.

Don’t kid yourself that your divorce will be different because you have a good relationship with your children’s mother. My ex-wife has become a dear friend and a superb partner in parenting. Despite the peculiar circumstance that ended our marriage, I couldn’t ask for a more thoughtful, accommodating woman to be my former spouse.

But as hard as we work to make it easier on our daughter, everything we can do is not enough. Even though my daughter has lived with me for the past couple of years, her being with me hasn’t changed the fact that our child lives in a house where one of her parents is missing. Divorce doesn’t just end a marriage—it ends a family.

By now I’ve lost almost everyone who has followed me this far. Most people will pity my naivete or denounce my blanket recommendation as insensitive and idiotic. So be it. It may not even be the type of argument that we can comprehend in our individualistic culture. We’ve become so accustomed to politically-oriented solutions for societal problems that we’ve forgotten that sometimes the only way to fix what we’ve broken is by individuals making tough choices. In this situation, there is no other way.

I can’t convince everyone, of course, but my hope is that there is at least one father left—even just one—who will seriously consider what I’m saying. I hope that he will go into his child’s room tonight and watch them while they sleep. I hope that he will think about what it means to his babies that he is there for them when they go to bed and that he is there for them when they wake up.

Finally, I hope he’ll realize he has the power to retain a precious gift that we visiting fathers have lost and that we can never get back. He still has the opportunity to be a good father.

Joe Carter is web editor of First Things.
Retrieved June 24, 2010 from http://www.firstthings.com/onthesquare/2010/06/dads-donrsquot-go


More about fatherhood:

Pamela Paul (2010). Are fathers necessary? http://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2010/07/are-fathers-necessary/8136/

W. Bradford Wilcox (2010). Are fathers really fungible? http://familyscholars.org/2010/06/14/are-fathers-really-fungible/

Andersson, Gunnar, 1962-
Noack, Turid.
Seierstad, Ane.
Weedon-Fekjaer, Harald.
The Demographics of Same-Sex Marriages in Norway and Sweden
Demography - Volume 43, Number 1, February 2006, pp. 79-98
Abstract at:

The present study investigates the demographics of same-sex marriages—that is, registered partnerships—in Norway and Sweden. We give an overview of the demographic characteristics of the spouses of these partnerships, study patterns of their divorce risks, and compare the dynamics of same-sex couples with those of heterosexual marriages. We use longitudinal information from the population registers of the two countries that cover all persons in partnerships. Our demographic analyses include information on characteristics such as age, sex, geographic background, experience of previous opposite-sex marriage, parenthood, and educational attainment of the partners involved. The results show that in many respects, the distributions of married populations on these characteristics differ by the sex composition of the couples. Patterns in divorce risks are rather similar in same-sex and opposite-sex marriages, but divorce-risk levels are considerably higher in same-sex marriages. The divorce risk for female partnerships is double that for male partnerships.

W. Bradford Wilcox (2009, April 13). To Have, to Hold, For a While
Amid divorce, remarriage and co-habitation, children do not do well.
http://online.wsj.com/article/SB123958524728412435.html

http://www.catholiceducation.org/articles/parenting/pa0140.htm
http://center.americanvalues.org/?p=78
http://www.firstthings.com/onthesquare/2009/06/on-the-demise-of-fatherhood
Fatherless America: Confronting Our Most Urgent Social Problem

Tuesday, June 22, 2010

Is U.S. Now On Slippery Slope To Tyranny?

Is U.S. Now On Slippery Slope To Tyranny? - Investors.com

Like many of Thomas Sowell's columns but unlike his more balanced and carefully argued book, A Conflict of Visions: Ideological Origins of Political Struggles, this op-ed is a bit over the top.

But his basic point, that Obama's leaning on BP for $20 billion of the corporation's money for use at the government's discretion to compensate victims of the oil spill is a threat to democracy, deserves more serious discussion than it is likely to get.

When governments can shake down corporations on such a scale as in this case, without due process of law or government respect for property rights, are they undermining democracy and the rule of law and promoting a slide to political, statist tyranny? A question to consider, at least in principle.

Sunday, June 20, 2010

Curmudgeonly Quotes 1

Knowledge is praised and desired by multitudes whom her charms could never rouse from the couch of sloth; whom the faintest invitation of pleasure draws away from their studies; to whom any other method of wearing the day is more eligible than the use of books, and who are more easily engaged by any conversation than such as may rectify their notions or enlarge their comprehension.
- Samuel Johnson, Rambler #178 (November 30, 1751)

The more I see of other people's children, the less I dislike my own. Evelyn Waugh

Satire is a sort of glass, wherein beholders do generally discover everybody's face but their own. - Jonathan Swift

We cannot learn without pain. - Aristotle

Optimists proclaim that we live in the best of all possible worlds; and pessimists fear this is true. - James Branch Cabell

brevis ipsa vita est sed malis fit longior
Life is short but misfortunes make it longer

corpora lente augescent cito extinguuntur
Bodies grow slowly and die quickly - Tacitus

Friday, June 11, 2010

Coercing Conscience: Professional Duty or Moral Integrity

“Does private conscience trump professional duty?” asks an editorial in the Journal of Medical Ethics (LaFollette & LaFollette, 2007, p.249). The answer for any person of integrity is yes, it must. In this essay, I want to defend that answer, although it is not the one given by the editorial or by the National Association of Social Workers (NASW) (2010) in the recent statement from its Legal Defense Fund.

The issue of coercing the conscience of professionals in the health and helping professions has come to the fore in recent years as a result of the discovery, invention, or promulgation of new rights in matters of life and death, but also sex, marriage, and family. Behaviors that were illegal or socially stigmatized for millennia have been declared legal and become rights. This is not simply a victory for tolerance against the views and values of the majority of the population. It is a claim, supported by the force of law, for equal recognition and respect, subject to anti-discrimination measures equivalent to those that apply in the case of sex and race.

For more than two millennia, physicians have sworn by the Hippocratic Oath not to engage or collude in practices like abortion, euthanasia, or assisted suicide that involve the deliberate taking of human life. In the twentieth century, the ethic of aiming always to heal, never to harm came under intense pressure, in the U.S. from the eugenics movement that, in alliance with the birth control movement led by Margaret Sanger sought to reduce the Black population, and medical experiments involving African-American airmen. This movement was taken up enthusiastically by the Nazis in Germany. In the wake of the serious violations of the Hippocratic ethic by Nazi physicians, the World Medical Association’s (1948) Physician’s Oath affirmed “I will maintain the utmost respect for human life from the time of conception, even under threat.” The legally binding United Nations Declaration of Human Rights and the 1959 UN Declaration of the Rights of the Child affirm the rights of the child before as well as after birth (Joseph, 2009). These reaffirmations of universal rights of adults and children were a strong response to the eugenics movement in the U.S. and Germany and the horrors of World War II that discredited it.

With astonishing speed, all these and other legal protections have been swept away in either letter or spirit. UN officials have been attempting to pressure sovereign member states to establish abortion as a legal right (Tozzi, 2008). Far from resisting these threats, professional associations have revised the Hippocratic and other oaths to eliminate the prohibitions on killing—whether through abortion, euthanasia, or assisted suicide. They have transformed their own professional ethics from forbidding abortion and other life-terminating measures to all but making direct or indirect participation in them a requirement of professional practice.

Many, indeed most people in the United States, and especially orthodox and observant religious individuals and communities, continue to regard abortion (at least in most circumstances) as a grave evil, assisted suicide and euthanasia as morally impermissible, marriage as the proper context for sex and for raising the children that result from it, homosexuality as intrinsically disordered, and sexual behavior (of any kind) outside marriage as wrong. These are the areas of greatest division in society, the battlegrounds of the culture wars in which state and civil society, professionals and their clients, elites and masses, are most commonly and sharply divided.

New rights, established mainly by judicial rulings, make previously forbidden behaviors lawful, thereby expanding the options for those who wish to engage in them. But what is optional behavior for clients or patients rapidly becomes mandatory for professionals in the form of participation or collusion in the newly permitted behavior.

One response is to acknowledge and protect the consciences of those practitioners who regard their own involvement (participation, collusion) in such behaviors as gravely evil. This is what conscience exemptions attempt to do. Freedom of conscience in these matters is often a matter of religious liberty and so, it is argued, protected by the First Amendment. You may have a legal right to an abortion but I have the right not to assist you in having one. Of course, many physicians, nurses, and social workers participate directly or indirectly in providing abortions and do so with untroubled consciences. But what allowance should be made for those to whom the practice is abhorrent and who wish to continue to practice according to the Hippocratic Oath as understood for many centuries down until the last one?

The argument against such conscience exemptions for health care professionals (physicians, nurses, social workers) is typically framed as a conflict between an individual’s (or institution’s) right to refuse treatment and patients’ rights to treatment. The client’s right to treatment, to a full range of services, may be linked to professionals’ willingness to provide them, especially in rural areas. As the chair of the ethics committee of the American College of Obstetrics and Gynecology put it, the “reproductive health needs” of women should trump the moral qualms of doctors (Bioedge, 2009).

In this discourse, the personal is contrasted with the professional, the idea being that a professional has a duty to provide whatever services are legal and demanded by clients. In this argument the conscience of the professional is invariably given short shrift and subordinated to the supposed rights of the client to treatment. I say “supposed” because it is not clear how the legal right to have an abortion in itself gives anyone a legal right to demand its provision, let alone anyone else’s legal obligation to carry it out.

In part, the failure of professional organizations like NASW to protect the conscience rights of their members is justified by an implicit rejection or belittling of the very concept of conscience as traditionally understood. In its place we find a contrast of public (or professional) and personal “values.” Here values have no intrinsic authority or foundation beyond being the opinions or beliefs of those who hold them. If this is so, then why should the personal opinions (values) of a practitioner not be subordinated to those of the state that licenses and funds the professional or institution? To see the logic of this position and how it corrupts ethical discourse in the professions, I want briefly to examine the concept of conscience in the context of abortion. This is far from the only issue at stake, but if a case for conscience exemptions cannot be made in the case of abortion, it cannot be made anywhere.

Conscience
Opponents of conscience exemptions give little or no weight to the gravity of requiring someone to act against their conscience or leave their profession or be denied admission to it and hence its schools. But the choice to act against your conscience can never be right. It is to choose to do what you believe to be wrong, and in the case of abortion, gravely wrong. If you are a Christian, it means to put your immortal soul in jeopardy; if a Catholic Christian, it means to excommunicate yourself from your Church and its sacraments.

For the orthodox Christian, if not for the secularist professionals who demand this sacrifice of moral integrity, these are matters of ultimate seriousness. But with or without such a religious framework for your life, it can never be right intentionally to do what you yourself believe to be wrong. Of course, you have a duty to inform your conscience on the material facts and moral issues involved. As a Catholic social worker, nurse, or physician, you particularly have the obligation to inform yourself about the authoritative teaching of the Church on the matter at hand. But in the end, as the Church herself teaches, your obligation is to follow your own conscience, even if that conscience is uninformed or in error. In that case, the fault is prior to the act in question; it lies in the failure to inform yourself or the error in your reasoning, not the decision to follow your conscience.

To require people to act against their conscience, that is to do intentionally what they know or believe to be wrong, is to require them to sacrifice their integrity. It sets up an opposition between professional duty and moral integrity. But can it really be a professional duty to act without integrity? What kind of profession is it that requires personal dishonesty and hypocrisy from its practitioners? What kind of state requires such moral corruption of the professionals and institutions it licenses?

Some opponents of conscience exemptions respond by saying fine, if you cannot in conscience meet the expectations and duties of the profession, leave it or choose a different line of work. This may indeed be the only option facing conscientious individuals where no accommodation is made. Conscience also trumps career.

Here it is noteworthy how the language of the anti-exemptionists is marvelously euphemistic. Abortion is part of the “full range” of “reproductive health care” or of meeting “reproductive health needs,” although it is anti-reproductive, is not (except in rare cases) about health, it is seldom remotely definable as a medical need, and it terminates care (and life) for one of the two patients involved. (In obstetrics textbooks, traditionally, the physician is said to have two patients, the mother and her unborn baby.) Proponents of abortion say they are not pro-abortion, but “pro-choice,” as if the taking of innocent human life were up to the person responsible for the care of that life.

Such are the ways that professionals who participate in abortion justify to themselves their violation of the Hippocratic Oath as understood for millennia, as they substitute ending life for healing. The word “killing,” in this context, is objectionable to supporters of abortion rights because they deny that the child in the womb is a person or human being. But for the persons whose conscience is to be coerced in the absence of adequate legal protection, killing, the deliberate taking of innocent human life, is precisely the action in which they are being told to participate. Dismissing their moral objections as personal qualms reduces the seriousness of the matter to something like squeamishness at the sight of blood.

But the rationalization that defines the fetus as less than fully human—like the past rationalization that justified on similar grounds “research” by American healing professionals on African-American airmen in Tuskegee or on Jewish prisoners by Nazi physicians—is no more persuasive to conscientious objectors to abortion than those earlier cases of grave professional malfeasance. The view seems not more but less and less tenable in light of scientific advances since Roe v. Wade that show ever more clearly that the fetus is a separate being with his or her own DNA and own principle of existence. It seems a truth not easily evaded without a level of self-deception that is itself morally corrupt that a fetus is what we all once were and we are alive now in part because our mothers did not have us killed at that stage of our lives (George & Tollefsen, 2008).

To require such self-deception of members of a profession is already to build dishonesty into its core. Less tendentiously, the kind of case against conscience clauses made by NASW, Hilary Rodham Clinton, and Planned Parenthood (Clinton & Richards, 2008) corrupts by trivializing conscience itself and reducing it to “personal values,” something idiosyncratic that the physician, nurse, and social worker have to check at the door when professional duty calls. It reduces the first axiom of all ethics, to do good and avoid evil, to something dispensable in face of the requirements of one’s profession. To exclude those who want to maintain their moral integrity in face of strong pressures to surrender it is to do further serious moral damage to the profession itself, as well as to the individuals and institutions excluded.

Note that this argument against exclusion does not depend on the empirical reality that religious professionals and institutions—e.g., Catholic physicians, nurses, social workers, and pharmacists as well as hospitals and clinics—play an important role in the American health care system. Their exclusion would involve a tremendous loss of talent, of knowledge, skill, aptitude, and dedication for the healing professions. It would also substantially reduce health care services of all kinds and therefore the access of patients to all such services. The argument here, rather, is that the coercion of conscience of professional health care providers is morally corrupting for the profession and its practitioners.

There are of course less draconian policy options. One idea is that the conscientious objector may be excused from direct involvement in a legal and available procedure like abortion, but must in the event of such refusal, refer the patient to others who are willing to perform it.

The argument for mandatory referral may appear persuasive at first glance, when it is posed in terms of the patient’s right to information about her options. But a refusal to refer a client to an abortionist is not the same as blocking her access to information. The fact that the mandatory referral alternative can be advanced as a reasonable solution—a compromise that any reasonable practitioner should be willing to accept—is one indication of the moral obtuseness of the opponents of strong conscience exemptions. It is a failure to take seriously the conscience and moral integrity of practitioners.

In the case of the life issues, the matter at stake is the fundamental moral proscription on the intentional taking of innocent human life. This has been a basic principle of ethics for millennia, an exceptionless norm which binds the consciences of all in societies where conscience is acknowledged at all. To kill justly requires at least that the person not be innocent (as in capital punishment or enemy soldiers in a just war); or not a fully human person (as has been argued by defenders of racism, anti-semitism, sexism, and abortion—see Brennan, 2000); or that killing is not the intent but an unintended, secondary side effect (as with deaths of nearby civilians from the bombing of a military target).

Some actions that result in the death of the unborn baby are indeed justifiable on the last of these grounds, as when a normal, necessary treatment for the mother’s cancer results in the foreseen but unintended death of her child or when both mother and child face imminent death and only one can be saved. In such rare cases, the death is not a result of abortion, which is the directly intended ending of the baby’s life. By this principle, some treatments for the effects of ectopic pregnancy directly kill the fetus in order to treat the mother, but others treat the mother with the foreseen but unintended effect of the child’s death. These are the hard cases that challenge ethicists to make fine yet vital distinctions. They are not the norm for the more than a million abortions carried out each year in the U.S. alone.

Of course, moral relativists, situationists, consequentialists, and ethical emotivists may deny the existence or binding nature of such a proscription on the killing of innocents. The ethicist and philosopher of animal rights Peter Singer agrees that there is no moral difference between a fetus and a fully born infant but, in line with his denial of human exceptionalism as a species, sees the intentional killing of either as justifiable in certain circumstances, even to save a healthy animal.

Here I will not take up the objections to these stances in moral philosophy, but simply note that if it is wrong to kill a person, then it is also wrong to get someone else to do it. If it is, as I believe, a grave evil for me to murder my spouse, it is no less wrong to hire someone else to do it for me. If it is wrong for me to help you kill your inconveniently long-lived rich parents, it is also wrong for me to refer you to a professional hit-man.

Opponents of conscience clauses and exemptions sometimes pose the matter in terms of religious professionals’ wanting to impose their views on clients or patients. This is a serious misunderstanding. None of the case for conscience exemptions has anything to do with imposing my will on the client, as anti-exemptionists and militant secularists often claim. Patients and clients have an uncontested moral right to informed consent and informed refusal.

But this is not the issue. The client may find abortion morally permissible and it is certainly legally permissible in the United States. I respect her right under law to decide to have an abortion and will not condemn, moralize, or argue with her. My right not to participate in what I believe is grave wrongdoing does not imply or depend on a right to impose my belief on the client. “Conscientious objection," as Pellegrino (2008) says, “implies the physician’s right not to participate in what she thinks morally wrong, even if the patient demands it. It does not presume the right to impose her will or conception of the good on the patient” (p.299).

References

Bioedge. ( January 2, 2009). Last-minute conscience rule grants protection to abortion objectors. Retrieved June 10, 2010 from http://www.bioedge.org/index.php/bioethics_article/8433

Brennan, W. (2000). Dehumanizing the vulnerable: When word games cost lives. Toronto, ON: Life Cycle Books.

Clinton, H.R., & Richards, C. (2008, September 19). Blocking care for women. New York Times. Retrieved November 20, 2008 from http://www.nytimes.com/2008/09/19/opinion/19clinton.html?sq=hillary%20clinton%20op-ed%20abortion&st=cse&scp=1&pagewanted=print

George, R.P., & Tollefsen, C. (2008). Embryo: A defense of human life. New York: Doubleday.

Joseph, R. (2009). Human rights and the unborn child. Leiden/Boston: Martinus Nijhoff.

LaFollette, E., & LaFollette, H. (2007). Private conscience, public acts. Journal of Medical Ethics, 33, 249-254.

National Association of Social Workers. (May, 2010). Legal Defense Fund. Social workers and conscience clauses. Legal Issue of the Month. Retrieved June 10, 2010 from https://www.socialworkers.org/ldf/legal_issue/2010/201005.asp?back=yes

Pellegrino, E.D. (2008). The philosophy of medicine reborn : A Pellegrino reader. H. T. Engelhardt, Jr., & F. Jotterand (Eds.). Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

Tozzi, P.A. (2008, November 28). Vatican tells United nations to quit pressuring countries to legalize abortion. LifeNews. Retrieved June 10, 2010 from http://www.lifenews.com/int1003.html

World Medical Association. (1948). Declaration of Geneva Physician's Oath. Retrieved June 16, 2010 from http://www.cirp.org/library/ethics/geneva/

The Philosophy of Medicine Reborn: A Pellegrino Reader (ND Studies in Medical Ethics)

Brennan, W. Dehumanizing the Vulnerable: When Word Games Take Lives

Brennan, W. John Paul II: Confronting the Language Empowering the Culture of Death

Embryo: A Defense of Human Life

Thursday, June 3, 2010

institutionalizing fatherlessness: birds, bees, and fertility clinics

A new report on young people who were conceived via anonymous sperm donor is available at:

http://www.familyscholars.org/assets/Donor_FINAL.pdf

where you can download all 140 pages

It is called My Daddy’s Name is Donor: A New Study of Young Adults Conceived through Sperm Donation
Elizabeth Marquardt, Norval Glenn, and Karen Clark, Co-Investigators

There is also an op-ed piece about the study at the NY Times, by Ross Douthat. It's at:

http://www.nytimes.com/2010/05/31/opinion/31douthat.html?partner=rssnyt&emc=rss